Monday, December 5, 2011

Hobbes, Montesquieu, and Rousseau – A Comparison of Views on Various Subjects


          The purpose of this paper is to compare the views of Hobbes, Montesquieu, and Rousseau on various subjects, to provide a critique of each philosopher’s position, and finally to argue for an alternative position.  The subjects explored, in order, are the relationships of freedom to law, nature and reason to God and revelation, commerce to virtue, and democracy to monarchy.  At the end of the paper, this author will provide his personal opinion on the various relationships and seek to synthesize, with modifications, the various philosophical stances into a practical, justifiable position that may serve as an alternative to the positions of the philosophers being critiqued.
On the relationship of freedom to law
Hobbes (From Leviathan)
Hobbes seems to make it clear in chapter five that freedom consists only in the absence of a physical hindrance to action when he states, “…if a man should talk to me of…any Free, but free from being hindered by opposition, I should…say…his words were without meaning; that is to say, Absurd1.”  This deterministic position is in full agreement with his mechanistic explanation of cause and effect, from object to sense, from sense to imagination, from imagination to speech, from speech to reason, and from there to the formation of the various passions, which are sought to be satisfied through endeavors, based on the individual’s appetites and aversions2.  Hobbes uses this definition of freedom to define liberty as “the absence of externall Impediments: which Impediments, may oft take away part of a mans power to do what he would; but cannot hinder him from using the power left him, according as his judgement, and reason shall dictate to him3.”  Because of Hobbes’ deterministic views on human behavior, the source of any willful human action is irrelevant when it comes to liberty.  All that matters is that the action is either unhindered by external barriers, and therefore the actor has the liberty to act, or it is hindered by external barriers, in which case the actor is denied liberty.  Hobbes reasserts his position more directly when, in chapter twenty-one, he describes what it means to be free.  “A Free-Man, is he, that in those things, which by his strength and wit he is able to do, is not hindered to doe what he has a will to do4.”
Hobbes divides laws into natural laws, which are existent at all times, and civil laws, which originate from a sovereign.  The two primary natural laws are articulated in chapter fourteen.  The first is, “That every man, ought to endeavour Peace, as farre as he has hope of obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use, all helps, and advantages of Warre5.”  The second is, “That a man be willing, when others are so too, as farre-forth, as for Peace, and defence of himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty against other men, as he would allow other men against himselfe6.”  Hobbes later states that the laws of nature are not truly laws, but are merely those qualities that dispose men to peace and obedience, and only become laws upon the creation of a common-wealth.  Immediately preceding this confession, Hobbes makes the assertion that the natural laws and civil laws are of “equall extent” and that natural laws are the commands of the common-wealth in the same manner the civil laws are the commands of the sovereign, and are at least equal in authority7.  Hobbes has previously implied that natural law has primacy over civil law, so when civil law stands in opposition to natural law, and seeks to deprive the person or people of their means to self-preservation and peace, people have recourse to natural law.  It is this primacy granted to natural laws that allows a reading of Hobbes that leads one to a conclusion that the people of a common-wealth have a right of revolution against the sovereign, by willfully entering into a state of nature (war) relative to the sovereign and those who remain in the common-wealth.
If one operates under the assumption that the natural rights and laws posited by Hobbes are ideals that right reasoning will lead one to follow, the only problem (though a major one) with his position is one of individual mental faculties.  This means that some people reason better than other people and any willful action to remove oneself from the common-wealth will always be arguably unreasonable, and would be argued as such by those who choose to remain a part of the common-wealth.  Of course, the reverse is also true, and one who removes himself from the common-wealth will argue that those remaining are unreasonable.  Hobbes has set himself up as the only true authority on what would be reasonable, and any who disagree with him are, as one can surmise from his tone in Leviathan, unreasonable.
Montesquieu (from The Spirit of the Laws) 
While Montesquieu may agree with Hobbes’ definition of liberty on the basis of the science of physics, Montesquieu chooses to define it in accordance with social governance, and gives two definitions.  The first definition provided is, “…liberty can consist only in having the power to do what one should want to do and in no way being constrained to do what one should not want to do.”  He explains this meaning further when he states, “Liberty is the right to do everything the law permit; and if one citizen could do what they forbid, he would no longer have liberty because the others would likewise have this same power.” Montesquieu goes on to define the particular type of liberty he is seeking to promote as political liberty, and it becomes obvious that Montesquieu has moved away from the Hobbesian understanding of liberty in terms of physics, Montesquieu provides the following definition: “Political liberty in a citizen is that tranquility of spirit which comes from the opinion each one has of his security, and in order for him to have this liberty the government must be such that one citizen cannot fear another citizen8.”  Montesquieu further claims that in order for a government to be such that it is capable of providing the citizens with this form of liberty it must be a moderate government and there must  be a separation of the three powers that Montesquieu sees in each state: the power of making, removing, and modifying laws, the power of making peace or war and dealing with foreign powers, and the power of punishment for crimes and judging disputes9. 
In determining how laws will best promote political liberty within republics, monarchies, and even despotisms, Montesquieu claims that each form of government will have different guiding principles (political virtue, honor, and fear, respectively10), its citizens will have different mores, and that laws need to be in agreement with and serve to promote those guiding principles, as well as take into account the climate, geography, religion, wealth, commerce, etc. of the people being governed11.  The number of variables involved when looking at any given culture, which serve to differentiate it from other cultures, make it impossible to apply any law universally, and Montesquieu implies this when he says, “Laws should be so appropriate to the people for whom they are made that it is very unlikely that the laws of one nation can suit another12.”  Montesquieu provides fifteen guidelines for how to approach laws when one seeks to determine the appropriateness for the given form of government and its principle, as well as for the people, taken as a whole, in book twenty-nine.  Montesquieu has done a brilliant job of identifying the fact that different people, having different ideas of right and wrong, and having needs and wants prioritized differently, will require governance that matches those ideas, needs, and priorities.  The primary problem with how he relates political liberty to the law is not the relation, but the definition he gives political liberty in the first place.  To make the claim that liberty is entirely dependent on the perception of fear by one citizen of another, and making the claim that the degree of liberty provided (reduction of fear) is the province of the law seems, to this author, improper.  In a world that has greatly improved (and will continue to improve) its understanding of brain chemistry and psychology it is entirely possible that at some point in time there could exist a chemical agent capable of removing the emotion of fear altogether.  Montesquieu also has not addressed the fear of what Hobbes would call “artificial men” in the form of government, governmental institutions, or corporations.  This is important because it is possible for a person to not fear the people of these organizations but fear the organizations themselves, seeing them as having a life of their own, separate from the people who are a part of it.
Rousseau (from On the Social Contract)
            Rousseau deals with three types of liberty: natural liberty, civil liberty, and moral liberty.  Natural liberty is the, “…natural freedom and an unlimited right to everything that tempts him and that he can get13.”  The transition of man from a state of nature, where natural liberty is enjoyed, into a civil state, results in civil liberty.  Whereas natural liberty is only limited by the amount of force one may bring to bear against any opposing force, civil liberty is limited, and defined by the general will.  This general will is a communal directive and is greater than the mere sum of the wills involved (which Rousseau would call the will of all) in the formation of the social contract.  Required for the social contract, and therefore civil liberty, is that each person give himself entirely to the community, and as everyone has equally vested themselves in the social contract, there is no private interest in making the contract onerous for others14.  Rousseau claims that by entering into this social contract and acquiring civil liberty through the body politic, it brings with it moral liberty.  According to Rousseau this transformation to civil society brings with it a redirection of the individual will toward the common will, “…by substituting justice for instinct in his behavior and giving his actions a morality they previously lacked.”  This moral liberty is the idea that, under Rousseau’s social contract, states people will be disposed to obedience to the laws they have prescribed for themselves, which is in direct opposition to natural liberty where natural laws were based on “impulse of appetite”, which Rousseau terms slavery, and is the sign of a “stupid, limited animal15.” 
            Rousseau has painted a picture of a utopian, idyllic society in which all laws are the result of the general will, designed to seek the common good, and always tend toward the public utility16.  With a society like the one Rousseau posits as resulting from the social contract in the way he sees it, it seems there would be no need for any laws, just decisions, which by the nature of the community would always be moral and right.  Even when one considers Rousseau’s admission that people can be misled, and therefore be mistaken when it comes to deliberating on their decisions, to assume as he does that factions and special interest groups can be made to have no greater power than any other group or individual, strikes this author as ludicrous utopianism.
On the relationship of nature and reason to God and revelation
Hobbes (From Leviathan)
            A reading of the first two parts of Leviathan would, by themselves, lend credence to the belief that Hobbes saw little, if any, good from a belief in God or in divine revelation.  However, the third part immediately shows that Hobbes may see nature and reason as God’s creations, and that all interpretation of things divine need to be made from a position of God-given reason, and with an understanding of the natural world.  In two statements Hobbes is clear that reason and nature are not in any way antithetical to God or revelation.  First, he states, “…we are not to renounce our Senses, and Experience; nor…our naturall Reason.  For they are the talents which he hath put into our hands to negotiate, till the coming again of our bleed Saviour17.”  Hobbes goes on to claim,
For though there be many things in Gods Word above Reason; that is to say, which cannot by naturall reason be either demonstrated, or confuted; yet there is nothing contrary to it; but when it seemeth so, the fault is either in our unskilfull Interpretation, or erroneous Ratiocination18.

By showing how nature, reason, God, and revelation are not mutually exclusive, Hobbes’ Leviathan may be interpreted from both secular, and scriptural, ecumenical perspectives.  Whether this speaks to Hobbes’ possible atheism or Lutheran belief system it is impossible to tell since he has tied the two belief systems together so well.  One potential benefit of doing what he has done here, is provide a method for civil governance for both the non-religious and religious.  One potential downfall of doing what he has done, is provide a justification for governance of any given religious doctrine.  However, this justification should not be taken to mean license for the sovereign to do as he pleases since Hobbes teaches that the laws of nature will remain in force; one of the foundational laws of nature being, “This is that Law of the Gospell; Whatsoever you require that others should do to you, that do ye to them19,” and is also known as the Silver Rule.  Furthermore, Hobbes asserts that until and unless a new prophet arises who both preaches the scripture unerringly and performs miracles, then there can be no credence given to the words of what would be obvious charlatans and deceivers20. 
Montesquieu (from The Spirit of the Laws)
            Montesquieu devotes two full books on the relationship between religion and governance, though religion is pervasive throughout the work.  There seems to be a general antipathy toward religion in general, but a practical concession that religion is so powerful and pervasive a force that any philosophy of government needs to accept and adapt to the religions and superstitious beliefs of the people to be governed.  Evidence for this interpretation of Montesquieu can be found in book eighteen, on laws and the nature of the terrain, where he includes superstition as a chapter, and states, “The prejudices of superstition are greater than all other prejudices, and its reasons greater than all other reasons21.”  In book four Montesquieu observes that the people in his time are exposed to education from three different sources: fathers, schoolmasters, and the world; and that the worldly education conflicts with that provided by the other two sources.  He explains this by saying, “This comes partly from the opposition there is for us between the ties of religion and those of the world22…”  In determining the part religion plays in governance, Montesquieu believes that as long as the laws are such that they regulate behavior and not thought or intent, they are less likely to lend themselves to unjust judgments against an accused, and a wrong removal of liberty, they are at least tolerable.  “For if the magistrate…even searches out hidden sacrilege, he brings an inquisition to a kind of action where it is not necessary; he destroys the liberty of the citizens23…”  This section makes it clear that in societies where religion exists at all, secular forces should see to it that civil laws do not punish religious transgressions, and that ecumenical authorities should have no authority to punish transgressions of civil laws.  This appears to be a precursor to the separation of church and state concept that is still argued over in the United States today.         
Rousseau (from On the Social Contract)
            Rousseau has set himself the task of determining, through reason, the best structure for a civil society, and the framework in which it must continually operate.  Beginning with his belief that man, in a state of nature, is an ignorant animal without language, without an understanding of moral values, and driven by emotion, he needs to apply reason to fix what is broken.  What is broken is that men have become “depraved” and “miserable” as a result of forming societies.  Rousseau believes that men, in this original state of nature where instinct was the dominant motivation for action, refrained from uselessly harming others, and chooses to use this as the basis for judging the “goodness” of human behavior24. 
            Rousseau makes the claim that all justice comes from God, but that without a social contract there is no means to see justice done, and this is the justification for the implementation of laws, the purpose of which is to see that justice is done among men.  Not only is Rousseau firm in his belief that God is the source of all justice, he seems convinced that the formation of a new state has always been accomplished by using the people’s religious beliefs to persuade them that the type of society being formed is better for them than their current state of existence.  Rousseau warns in this section that “one must not conclude from all this…that politics and religion have a common object for us, but rather that at the origin of nations, one serves as an instrument of the other25.”  In fact, he later asserts that at first all governments were theocratic, and needed to be in order to provide the justification for the formation of a united society26.
            In the same chapter, Rousseau explains why a religion in a state is more useful than not having one, and why Christian law is more harmful than useful: especially Roman Catholicism, which he sees as so bad he doesn’t discuss the reasons in depth, claiming it’s a waste of time to do so.  He does, however, state that a type of Christianity, “not that of today, but that of the Gospel (is a)…saintly, sublime, true religion,” but still shows how it is inconsistent with a good state since true believers are more interested in the afterlife and salvation than they are of their life in the state, and the state suffers as a result of this27.
            In order to create what Rousseau sees as the strongest possible state, he explains that the state should have a civil religion which should establish “sentiments of sociability without which it is impossible to be a good citizen or a faithful subject28.”  This religion should not be compulsory, though the sovereign is within his rights to banish anyone who does not believe in it, and it should have minimal dogmas.  Rousseau suggests the following dogmas, “The existence of a powerful, intelligent, beneficent, foresighted, and providential divinity; the afterlife, the happiness of the just; the punishment of the wicked; the sanctity of the social contract and the laws…” He describes these as positive dogmas, and provides one negative dogma of intolerance.  The negative dogma of intolerance is so important to a strongly constituted state that Rousseau warns about the dangers of allowing intolerance in strong terms. 
Those who make a distinction between civil and theological intolerance are mistaken, in my opinion.  These two intolerances are inseparable.  It is impossible to live in peace with people whom one believes to be damned.  To love them would be to hate God who punishes them.  They must absolutely be either brought into the faith or tormented.  Whenever theological intolerance exists, it is impossible for it to not have some civil effect; and as soon as it does, the sovereign is no longer sovereign, even over temporal matters.  From then on, priests are the true masters; kings are merely their officers29.

The only time Rousseau agrees that it may be right for the priests to be the “true masters” as he called them, above, is when the “state is the church, and the prince is the pontif.”  In any other form of government, any and all religious beliefs should be tolerated to the extent that their dogmas are not in opposition to the duties and obligations of the citizenry, and as long as they are tolerant of all other faiths.  Any religion or faith that violates this rule should be removed from the state30.
On the relationship of commerce to virtue
Hobbes (From Leviathan)
            Hobbes dismisses the ancient understanding of virtue as a moderate point between two extremes and redefines what virtue is from his mechanistic basis for human understanding, and bases the definition on the action itself and the propensity of a man to perform those actions in accordance with a given virtue or defect.  Virtue and its opposite, defect, are either natural or acquired, and are related directly to the intellect31.  Natural wit is acquired through use, and acquired wit is acquired through instruction, with each responsible for the particular virtues and defects of a person.  Proper use of a person’s wit would be virtuous and tend to provide for one’s security and self-preservation while improper use would be defective and tend to diminish one’s security, putting his own preservation at risk.  Only through proper reasoning will a person reach the right conclusion. 
For those in a common-wealth, where commerce would be permitted32 by the ideal sovereign who would use force to see that violations of civil and natural laws are punished, adherence to natural laws (also called moral laws) is compulsory.  Hobbes states that the third natural law is justice, which is simply stated: “That men performe their Covenants made33.”  As commerce is, at its core, the result of mutual covenants of trust, it is protected in a common-wealth by a sovereign, and protected in a state of nature by God.  This is made clear at the end of chapter fifteen where Hobbes says of the laws of nature, “…Law, properly is the word of him, that by right hath command over others.  Yet if we consider the same Theoremes, as delivered in the word of God, that by right commandeth all things; then are they properly called Lawes34.”  One might claim that the laws of nature are not the same as the civil laws governing commerce, but Hobbes instructs the reader in chapter twenty-six that, “The Law of Nature, and the Civill Law, contain each other, and are of equall extent…,” and that once a common-wealth is created the natural laws become civil laws and are the “commands of the Common-wealth35.”  These commands, in this case, are that justice be done according to the laws.  Injustice is the failure to adhere to a covenant, so if there is a covenant or compact, the adherence to it by all involved parties is the relevant definition of justice36.    
Montesquieu (from The Spirit of the Laws)
              Montesquieu says that each form of government should govern according to particular guiding principles.  In a republic the guiding principle is virtue, specifically political virtue (with a spirit of equality present in democracies, and a spirit of moderation in aristocracies), in a monarchy it is honor, and in despotism it is fear.  For the purposes of how virtue relates to commerce in each of these systems, or even in general, it is best in this writer’s opinion to consider each guiding principle as a virtue in its own right, as odd as it may seem to consider fear as a virtue.  Consider that the guiding principle in each form of government is that which keeps the government stable, and for this reason should be considered a requisite virtue. 
Political virtue is a love of the laws and the state, and requires a constant preference for the common good over one’s own37.  Honor is oriented toward the self, and is measured by the degree to which one has most acquired “a gracious manner, a courtly air, intelligence, good judgment, politeness, urbanity, and joyfulness – and all this without constraint, affectation, or defect of any kind,” and would be a perfect honette homme38.  In this way, and according to the rules of honor in the monarchy, a social hierarchy is established with the prince above all.  Fear serves to keep the people as slaves, serving the whims and caprices of the despot.  However, for stable despotisms there must be some stability, and for a despotic government to be tractable, it must be forced through some means to follow some order and suffer some rule39.
According to Montesquieu commerce, in general, gentles the mores of a people, though the laws of commerce may either perfect the mores or ruin the mores.  Commerce also tends to lead to peace between different states, though not between individuals40.  Montesquieu sees commerce as a force that at times is more powerful than the sovereigns, saying, “Commerce, sometimes destroyed by conquerors, sometimes hampered by monarchs, wanders across the earth, flees from where it is oppressed, and remains where it is left to breath41.”  After letters of exchange began circulating, allowing people to hide their wealth more effectively, “Since that time princes have had to govern themselves more wisely than they themselves would have thought, for it turned out that great acts of authority were so clumsy that experience itself has made known that only goodness of government brings prosperity42.”  Montesquieu further states the specific purpose of commerce is “to export and import commodities in favor of the state43.”
  Republics are most welcoming to commerce, and republics that have commerce as their foundation may experience great wealth without the people’s mores being damaged, “because the spirit of commerce brings with it the spirit of frugality, economy, moderation, work, wisdom, tranquility, order, and rule.  Thus, as long as this spirit continues to exist, the wealth it produces has no bad effect.”  This spirit can be maintained as long as the laws provide that fortunes are divided “in proportion as commerce increases them, (and) must make each poor citizen comfortable enough to be able to work as the others do and must bring each rich citizen to a middle level such that he needs to work in order to preserve or to acquire44.”
Monarchies should limit commerce in a few ways.  The nobles should not be permitted to levy taxes, as they would then be in the position of a despot where the people have no higher authority to appeal to and the nobles appointed to relieve any abuses would like to reap the benefits of those abuses.  Nobles should refrain from engaging in commerce since it could result in their acquisition of exorbitant and unseemly amounts of wealth, which Montesquieu deems as pernicious45.
Regarding commerce in despotic states, Montesquieu only has this to say, “As for the despotic state, it is useless to talk about it.  General rule: in a nation that is in servitude, one works more to preserve than to acquire; in a free nation, one works more to acquire than to preserve46.” 
Rousseau (from On the Social Contract)
            Rousseau believes the general will is that will directed toward the greatest common good.  In book two he states, “the greatest good of all…comes down to these two principle objects: freedom and equality47.”  Rousseau then says that, presuming moderation of avarice within the lower classes and moderation of goods and influence in the upper classes, that people should be relatively equal.  In his note on the subject he asserts that this is done for the stability of the state.  “…tolerate neither opulent people nor beggars.  These two conditions, naturally inseparable, are equally fatal to the common good.  From the one come those who foment tyranny and from the other the tyrants48.”
            Commerce within a state, between its citizens, with the intent to increase one’s wealth and luxuries, are not conducive to the common good, and therefore could not be something the general will would support.  Rousseau asserts, “Give money and you will soon have chains.  The word finance is a slave’s word…In a truly free State the citizens do everything with their hands and nothing with money49.”  Rousseau is not opposed entirely to trade between nations, if it serves the common good, though he believes that it is unsustainable and the society will eventually stop trading.  Rousseau again seems to be quite similar to Montesquieu when he lists a series of suggestions based on a state’s geography, climate, customs, and character of its citizens.  One suggestion to a hypothetical state with an extensive shoreline is, “Cover the sea with ships; cultivate commerce and navigation.  You will have a brilliant and brief existence.”  Rousseau gives a note here regarding foreign commerce where he refers to the Marquis d’Argenson, who said “foreign commerce…creates almost nothing but a deceptive utility for a kingdom in general.  It can enrich some private individuals, even some towns; but the whole nation gains nothing from it and the people is not better off because of it50.”  It seems Rousseau finds virtue and commerce two things that do not mix well, unless it is in a very particular situation, and then it they only mix well for a very limited time.
On the relationship of democracy to monarchy
Hobbes (From Leviathan)
Hobbes criticized Aristotle’s division of government forms, both the good and bad as Aristotle sees them; kingship v. tyranny, aristocracy v. oligarchy, and polity v. democracy.  Hobbes asserts that Aristotle has made a mistake in his classifications by calling a government that has the exact same structure two different things depending on the intent of the ruler or rulers.  Hobbes blames this error of discernment on Aristotle’s moral values creating a perception bias51.  Hobbes gives the impression that he will rank the various forms, of which there are only three in his opinion, monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, based on reason, and not on virtue as Aristotle did.  Interestingly enough, it also appears that Hobbes may have merely been using a bit of rhetoric to sweep aside old ideas to replace them with new ones, again.  As he begins his ranking by discussing monarchy, he almost immediately brings in questions of virtue with the use of words like “corrupt” and have meanings grounded in moral values. 
            Hobbes deals with monarchies first, and claims that a good monarch is far better than corrupt legislators.  Misleading, considering he doesn’t make the comparison with good legislators, or with a corrupt monarch.  At first glance, however, an argument could be made that even a good monarch might be better than a group of mostly good legislators because there is no dilution of responsibility for the actions of the ruler in a monarchy amongst other rulers like there is with a legislature, therefore, as Hobbes claims, the interests of one good monarch are more closely aligned with the interests of the society than are any other form of government where many more people would be involved in lawmaking.  The primary problem here would be that the one good ruler is compared to a mostly good legislature, without giving any thought, at this time, to the results of one corrupt ruler in opposition to a majority of corrupt legislators.
            By comparing this “bad” possible eventuality with the good one, reason would show that a few good legislators would have a better chance of mitigating corruption in government by the corrupt ones, leaving society in a better condition than if it were to suffer under the effects of one corrupt monarch, where there is no mitigating, equal force at the legislative level.  Hobbes later addresses the potential problems with succession in a monarchy and the inherent risk that a monarchy, due to a succession crisis, could more easily dissolve back into a state of nature52.  If the litmus test for determining the most favorable form of government is that it must be most resistant to dissolution that would result in society reverting to a state of nature, then monarchy would be the least favorable of the three forms of government Hobbes addresses. So, while a surface understanding of Leviathan might lead one to believe that Hobbes believes that a monarchy is the “best” form of government, with a deeper understanding it can be concluded that he actually is supporting a republic as the best form. 
Montesquieu (from The Spirit of the Laws)
            A quick reading of Montesquieu would seem to indicate that he is taking a wholly relativistic approach to which form of government would be best, whether despotic, monarchal, or republican.  Much of The Spirit of the Laws concerns itself with how to apply the variables that Montesquieu believes should make up a government, such as climate (books 14-17), terrain (book 18), commerce, population, spirit, mores, manners, and religion of the people (books 19-25).  However, in book eleven, “On the laws that form political liberty in its relation with the constitution,” a close reading will show that Montesquieu appears to begin to lose his non-judgmental stance and start to show some favoritism for a republican form of government over a monarchal form.
            Book eleven is where Montesquieu delineates the three types of power always present in a state: legislative, executive (dealing with the rights of nations), and executive (dealing with the civil rights, which he simply calls judging53).  In a section on how the power of judging should be applied in criminal cases, after he suggests that an accused should have the ability to challenge his judges, where those remaining are considered to be those acceptable to the accused, he states, “The two other powers may be given instead to magistrates or permanent bodies because they are exercised upon no individual, the one being only the general will of the state, and the other, the execution of that general will54.”  Montesquieu does not define what he means when he uses the term “general will.”  It seems likely to this author that the general will Montesquieu speaks of is the same general will Rousseau defines in On The Social Contract published fourteen years after Montesquieu’s The Spirit of the Laws.  If this is the case, then the general will is that of the people.  This seems correct in at least one other way, when the concept of sovereignty is explored.  A despot is the sovereign in a despotic government.  The people are the sovereign in a republic.  An absolute monarch is, for all practical purposes, a despot, or is likely to become one even if the monarch did not at first wield his power arbitrarily.  The type of monarchy Montesquieu is focused on is the constitutional monarchy, like England was at the time, and sovereignty seems to be divided between the monarch, the nobles, and intermediary powers.  Sovereignty cannot be divided and risk being in opposition to itself (which is impossible, and any appearance to that effect would be the result of private interests being misunderstood to be the general will), so sovereignty must reside in the people, and expressed through the general will, even in a monarchy, if Montesquieu is to be understood correctly.
Rousseau (from On the Social Contract)
            When it comes to a true democracy Rousseau rightly asserts, “In the strict sense of the term, a true democracy has never existed and never will exist.  It is contrary to the natural order that the majority govern and the minority be governed55.”  Rousseau then proceeds to list a number of prerequisites for a democracy in order to be successful: a small state, simplicity of morals, equality in ranks and fortunes, little or no luxury, and most importantly virtue56.  It may then be assumed that the only form of democratic government warranting consideration is of an aristocratic form, of which Rousseau delineates three types: natural, elective, and hereditary.  Of these three types, the preferred, and the one to be compared to the ideal monarchy, is the elective form.  In this case, Rousseau determines that in a popular government where all men are equally magistrates, an aristocracy is such that the people elect those who are believed to the wisest and most fit to govern the citizens.  However, as a result of some inherent inequities of power and wealth within an aristocracy, Rousseau states that a nation governed democratically, through an elected aristocracy, requires “…moderation among the rich and contentment among the poor,” since an aristocracy does not require the level of virtue a true democracy would need.
            When Rousseau examines monarchal forms of government, the implication is that there are so many inherent risks in a monarchy that it cannot be the preferred form of government.  This is reminiscent of Hobbes comparison of monarchy to a republic.  Hobbes’ concern seemed to be sustainability, and the conclusion he implies was eventually reached by way of analyzing the risks inherent in monarchies when it comes to transfers of power and the rights of succession.  With Rousseau one sees the same risk assessment at the core of his discussion.  The following quotes give strong evidence that Rousseau would firmly support any elected aristocracy over a monarchy.
“…if no other government has more vigor, there is none where the private will has greater sway and more easily dominated the others.” 

“Kings want to be absolute…”

“The best kings want to be able to be wicked if it so pleases them, without ceasing to be the masters.”

“Their personal interest is first of all that the people should be weak, miserable, and unable ever to offer any resistance to them.”

Finally, Rousseau delivers a coup de grâce to monarchies when he states an outright conclusion to the question of preference of monarchies or democracies with,
An essential and inevitable defect, which will always place monarchical government below republican, is that in the latter the public voice almost never raises to high positions any but enlightened, capable men, who fulfill them with honor; whereas those who attain them in monarchies are most often merely petty troublemakers, petty rascals, petty intriguers, whose petty talents--which lead to high positions in royal courts—serve only to reveal their ineptitude to the people as soon as these men are in place.  The people makes a mistake in its choice much less often than the prince, and a man of real merit is nearly as rare in a ministry as a fool at the head of a republican government57.

Author’s synthesis of the aforementioned theories and relationships  
 Understand that the following interpretations and suggestions are based on a somewhat parochial perspective from one who has a predisposed bias toward certain concepts of freedom, law, the natural world, spirituality and religion, and governmental structures, which stem from a combination of cultural inculcation and experience, and only afterward are followed by independent reasoning over the course of nearly forty years.  I need to acknowledge that the interrelationships of the various concepts and ideals need to be addressed with a Montesquieu-like moderation, as an excess in any direction will lead to a failure to reach the ideal ends of any society, which is a balance of liberty and security that may be maintained indefinitely, and like Rousseau reasons, takes into account human nature as it is, and as it may become.
Regarding liberty and law, there should first be a guiding principle within the people that tends toward three things.  First, there should be a general desire of the people to associate with other citizens in a civil, non-violent manner, where each person’s physical being and property is regarded with the utmost respect.  Second, people should desire to improve their state, their immediate community, themselves, and all other peoples of the world (in that order) in ways that will not harm others physically, financially, or emotionally.   Third, the people should be always vigilant and prepared to oppose any who put private interests above the general interest, which would be in opposition to the general will.  All of the above require, as Montesquieu points out, a certain political virtue to be taught to all in such a way that it tends to inspire the public to seek the general will and understand the principles upon which the society rests.  I think at this point it is obvious that Rousseau’s concept of the general will is one I agree with wholeheartedly as a requirement for a stable society.  Unfortunately, the ability to discern what laws and what decisions are most in accordance with the general will is still somewhat problematic.
I disagree with Rousseau that a religion is necessary for a civil state, but understand the power any religion can have on the mores and the desires of a people.  I do agree with Hobbes’ stance that a civil society does not need to be one that dismisses the possibility of divine revelation or the possibility of divine laws.  However, in order to best be able to incorporate differences in religious beliefs Rousseau is correct in asserting that tolerance is mandatory.  Without tolerance of different beliefs, the visceral nature of the emotions religion is capable of inspiring is a threat not only to those with diametrically opposed spiritual beliefs, but it can be a threat to everyone within the state.  Hobbes suggestion that laws be made based on the understanding that not everyone who has claimed divine revelation agrees with each other on dogma, and is further correct that it would be improper to hold culpable for violations of law based on divine revelation those who have either not been privy to the same revelation in the same way, or who claim an experience of a different revelation.  Therefore, it must be that in order to best govern a society, the laws must devolve to only the common ground each citizen can find agreement with.  In the hypothetical posed here, that would be in accordance with the general will, and incorporate Hobbes second natural law that one refrain from doing to others what he would not have done to him.
Montesquieu and Rousseau both have similar beliefs when it comes to the amount of damage excesses of luxury can cause a state.  If the ability for acquisition is left unchecked, and allows for the possibility that any one person, or any one faction of people, may acquire so much that people are beholden to them for their own well being, then that possibility, beyond being minimized and mitigated, needs instead to be eliminated altogether.  This is not to say that any and all luxury is to be eliminated.  Such a suggestion goes so against man’s natural inclinations to seek luxury that it would be a ridiculous and doomed endeavor from the start.  Instead, as both philosophers suggest, for practical considerations there needs to be a range of economic conditions that range from the mere level of subsistence on the low end to the high end where luxuries and indolence may be enjoyed by those who have worked for and earned them, but will not be so provided for that regular and productive labor is not necessary to maintain the luxuries enjoyed. 
When it comes to an ideal form of government, to see to the ends I’ve proposed, I must agree with Hobbes (based on what I believe his preference to be), Montesquieu, and Rousseau, in that a democracy, by way of aristocratic form (representative republic), with the separation of powers, is the preferable form.  Considering that I believe the U.S. has this particular form, it cannot help but be wondered, what is lacking that might explain the ills seen in our country.  The answer is several things.  While Montesquieu and Rousseau would probably point to the size of our country as being the primary cause, I would disagree with them on that point.  I would point to two large ideological factions that believe America is virtuous, and further believe in the concept of American exceptionalism.  One particular group sees virtue from a belief that Americans are inherently good, moral individuals and superior to other states and cultures from that perspective.  The other group sees virtue from a belief that our system of checks and balances, combined with the guiding principles of equality and justice that America’s founding documents espouse, with an understanding that different people will see things as being “good” or “bad” from different perspectives.  The two beliefs, regardless of the fact that one may or may not be more worthy than the other, are antithetical in nature.  The first group places sees virtue and morality as the result of nationality, while the second group sees virtue and morality as a result of adherence to what they believe to be universal principles and the ability of people to work together to minimize abuses of power through a properly designed and monitored system of governance.  It might be too late to rectify the disparate beliefs of these two factions, but if it is not, the only way it can be rectified is, as Montesquieu claims is mandatory for a state to properly pursue its guiding principles, education.  In the case of the United States, required is a state education that promotes political virtue, the general will, and equality, fairness and justice.




Citations
1.     Leviathan. Ch 5. p. 113
2.     Leviathan. Ch 1-6. p. 85-130
3.     Leviathan. Ch 14. p. 189
4.     Leviathan. Ch 21. p. 262
5.     Leviathan. Ch 14. p. 190
6.     Leviathan. Ch 14. p. 190
7.     Leviathan. Ch 26. p. 314
8.     The Spirit of the Laws. Part 2. Book 11. Ch 6. pp. 155, 157
9.     The Spirit of the Laws. Part 2. Book 11. Ch 6. pp. 156-157
10.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 3. pp. 21-28
11.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 1. Ch 3. pp. 8-9
12.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 1. Ch 3. pp. 8
13.  On the Social Contract. Book 1. Ch 8. p. 56
14.  On the Social Contract. Book 1. Ch 6. p. 53
15.  On the Social Contract. Book 1. Ch 8. p. 56
16.  On the Social Contract. Book 2. Ch 3. p. 61
17.  Leviathan. Ch 32. p. 409
18.  Leviathan. Ch 32. pp. 409-410
19.  Leviathan. Ch 14. p. 190
20.  Leviathan. Ch 32. pp. 413-414
21.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 3. Book 18. Ch 18. p. 294
22.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 4. Ch 4. p. 35
23.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 2. Book 12. Ch 4. p. 190
24.  On the Social Contract. Introduction. p. 7
25.  On the Social Contract. Book 2. Ch 7. p. 70
26.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 8. p. 124
27.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 8. p. 130
28.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 8. p. 130
29.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 8. p. 131
30.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 8. p. 132
31.  Leviathan. Ch 8. p. 134
32.  Leviathan. Ch 21. p. 264
33.  Leviathan. Ch 15. p. 202
34.  Leviathan. Ch 15. p. 217
35.  Leviathan. Ch 26. p. 314
36.  Leviathan. Ch 15. p. 202
37.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 4. Ch 5. p. 36
38.  Stanton, Domna C. The Aristocrat as Art: A Study of the Honnete Homme and the Dandy in Seventeenth and Nineteenth-Century French Literature, by Domna C. Stanton. Columbia University Press. Oct 15, 1980. p. 52
39.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 8. Ch 10. p. 119
40.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 4. Book 20. Ch 1-2. p. 338
41.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 4. Book 21. Ch 5. p. 356
42.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 4. Book 21. Ch 20. p. 389
43.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 4. Book 20. Ch 13. p. 346
44.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 5. Ch 6. p. 48
45.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 1. Book 5. Ch 8. pp. 53-54
46.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 4. Book 20. Ch 4. p. 341
47.  On the Social Contract. Book 2. Ch 11. p. 75
48.  On the Social Contract. Book 2. Ch 11. p. 75
49.  On the Social Contract. Book 4. Ch 15. p. 102
50.  On the Social Contract. Book 2. Ch 12. p. 76
51.  Leviathan. Ch 19. pp. 239-241
52.  Leviathan. Ch 19. pp. 241-246
53.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 2. Book 11. Ch 6. p. 156-157
54.  The Spirit of the Laws. Part 2. Book 11. Ch 6. p. 158
55.  On the Social Contract. Book 3. Ch 4. p. 85
56.  On the Social Contract. Book 3. Ch 4. p. 85
On the Social Contract. Book 3. Ch 6. p. 87-89

Wednesday, October 12, 2011

John Locke's 2nd Treatise - My Interpretation

Locke bases his arguments regarding political power and laws on his belief that early man’s initial existence was in a state of nature, where all are equal in authority, none having the right of dominion over another, and all enjoy the natural right to perfect liberty1.  This state of nature is governed by the laws of nature.  He asserts the laws of nature, governed by reason, require that each act in a manner consistent with his self-preservation, and do no harm to another’s life, health, liberty or possessions2.  He further explains that if a man is in competition with another, he is obligated to see to his self-preservation first, and when not in competition with another it is his duty to see to the preservation of others3.  When all in a state of nature obey the laws of nature, peace is assured.  In a state of nature, with all men equal and none having superiority over the other, each individual has the natural right to justly punish those who are in violation of the laws of nature, giving natural law force, as those who have violated a law have set themselves outside of the law and is a danger to mankind4.  This is how, in a state of nature, one comes to have lawful power over another, and may do harm to him for reparation and restraint, according to calm reason and the dictates of conscience5.
Locke identifies the problem with this execution of the natural laws when he acknowledges that it is unreasonable for the one wronged by a violation of the law by another to be the one executing the law, seeking redress and restraint through punishment, because they are likely to be ruled by their passions and not dispassionate reason.  Locke then asserts that the correct remedy is civil government6.  He goes on to state that in cases of absolute monarchy, where one person has the authority and liberty to judge in his own cases, and may do to the citizens whatever he wishes, it would be better to revert back to a state of nature than to suffer the rule of such a civil government7.   He reaches this conclusion as a result of how he sees absolute monarchs.  He sees them as being in a state of nature in relation to other sovereigns, and in a state of nature in relation to their subjects, because they are not a part of a political body, but are outside it since they do not consider themselves to be a part of the community of sovereigns or their subjects.  A state of nature is where all men exist until they willingly consent to make themselves a part of a political community or society8.  Locke then ties all of the aforementioned principles together, with the principle of consent being paramount for civil society, when he states, “The liberty of man, in society, is to be under no other legislative power, but that established, by consent, in the commonwealth, nor under the dominion of any will, or restraint of any law, but what the legislative shall enact according to the trust put in it.”9 (Emphasis added) One of the most important aspects of the legislative power, according to Locke, is that it is limited to the public good of the society10.   Locke explicitly states that the power of enacting laws granted to the legislators can, because they’ve been granted through trust in the first place, be revoked by the people and given to new legislators when the trust has been violated11.  It is because of this that the sovereign, who has the granted, legitimate right of making laws, enters into a compact with the rest of society to see to the protection of the property of all the subjects may, by violating the trust put in him and failing to pursue the public good, have the power and authority of lawmaking removed from him and granted to another. 
As can be seen, Locke’s foundation for government and law is one based on his interpretation of natural rights and natural laws that lead him to some very important conclusions.  First, the power and authority to act to the limits of one’s capabilities is held equally by all individuals in a state of nature, and each person is obligated by natural law to direct that power in a way that promotes and protects one’s health, life, and property.  Second, in order to move away from a state of nature and its attendant risks and dangers to one’s self-preservation, people choose to enter into a compact and create a civil government where they willingly grant some of their natural rights, power, and authority to a commonwealth (the body of people as a whole), which in turn cedes those rights to a sovereign who will be supported in the execution of civil law and who, in return for this authority, enters into an agreement with the populace to use the authority for the benefit of the common good.  Third, the authority granted, because it is a natural possession of the people, may be taken back by the people if they believe the sovereign is in violation of the agreement, and then give those powers to another. 
The above three points deal specifically with the transfer of natural rights (inherent individual power) from the people and to a sovereign, under natural law, through agreement.  As can be extrapolated from Locke’s basic foundation, the form of a sovereign power is irrelevant.  The above can be applied satisfactorily to any form of government whether a democracy, monarchy, or aristocracy.  In each form of government the people have the natural right, as individuals to leave civil society and enter into a state of nature/war against the sovereign and the rest of society, or as a collective to remove their granted powers from the sovereign by any means necessary and grant them to another.  Furthermore, because of the nature of the sovereign’s responsibility to execute laws, the sovereign will have more resources at his disposal, operating under his direction and at his discretion, than anyone, or any few members of the community with which he is in compact with.  This will create an imbalance of power such that it is likely that only when a majority of the community is willing to revoke their power and replace the sovereign will it happen.  Until that point is reached, the people, by not revoking their granted powers to the sovereign, are giving tacit approval for the sovereign and would need to be seen as opposing any who seek to enter into a state of war against the sovereign.  This requirement of a majority, in either direction, is what makes the principles Locke espouses, at their core, democratic in nature even while not requiring a democrat form for the government.
At this point it needs to be explained that two distinct powers, previously discussed, are held by a sovereign: legislative power and executive power.  One power, the executive, is that power to act according to natural rights and natural laws, in a manner that promotes self-preservation (of the community and its members), and it exists both in a state of nature and in a state of civil society12.  The other power, the legislative, is the power to make laws that restrict action in order to promote the self-preservation of all, for the common good, by determining how executive force is to be applied in the furtherance of that end, and only exists in a state of civil society as a power that comes into existence as a result of the social contract between the people and the sovereign13.  These powers may be held jointly by one, as is the case in absolute monarchies, or they may be held by two or more distinct civil authorities as they are in the United States. 
Upon the agreement of a community of individuals to create a commonwealth, there is a created, second power that comes into existence at the same time as the legislative power: the federative.  As an individual has a natural right to see to his self-preservation, so too does a commonwealth as an individual entity, or construct, have the same natural rights to see to its self-preservation.  The power of a commonwealth to exercise these extrapolated natural rights are called Federative and is an acknowledgment that as a community, separate from other communities, having only entered into a compact amongst themselves, excluding outsiders, it is still in a state of nature in relation to those outside powers, whether they be individuals or other commonwealths14.   This direct quote most eloquently and succinctly states both the limits and extent of the federative powers.  “This therefore contains the power of war and peace, leagues and alliances, and all the transactions, with all persons and communities without the commonwealth…”15 The execution of federative powers, being such that they are the powers of the commonwealth as a whole, taken as a single entity, and for the common good, may at times operate outside of any specific laws or even in violation of laws already agreed upon.  This conflict, though more readily apparent in the exercise of federative power than executive because of the scrutiny under which it operates, is more prone to being interpreted in the moment by the immediate passions of the individuals of the commonwealth, with their accompanying biases, than an act that is perceived to be just because it is done in accordance with, and therefore restricted by, previously enacted positive law.
The Wall Street Journal reported, on October 12, 2011, the foiling of an Iranian attempt to bomb a fictitious restaurant where a Saudi diplomat was alleged to spend time, as well as the Saudi and Israeli embassies in Washington, D.C16.   The U.S. has already issued sanctions as a result of the event, and has stated Iran would be held accountable for this attempted terrorist attack.  The U.S. has several options through the use of executive and federative power as a response goes.  How the public perceives the response in terms of promoting the common good and self-preservation will be a key factor in the decision-making process to determine what action should be taken.  One possible response, extreme though it is, would be to retaliate with a full scale nuclear strike, forever eliminating Iran as a threat to the commonwealth.  Another possible response would be for the commonwealth to issue a verbal rebuke and censure the Iranian government for its actions, which could easily be seen as the opposite extreme.       
While some may see an inherent tension between the exercise of executive and federative power and the principles of democracy, a thorough understanding of Locke’s foundation should remove that concern.  Democracy is defined as “Government by the people; that form of government in which the sovereign power resides in the people as a whole, and is exercised either directly by them (as in the small republics of antiquity) or by officers elected by them.”17   It has already been shown that, according to Locke, sovereign power is a natural right of each individual, and though some of that power and authority (the right to act) have been ceded through the social contract and granted, for a time and for a specific end, to an external authority, those rights may be revoked by the individuals, and in effect by the community at large when it is determined the sovereign is in violation of his obligations under the agreement.  This is the core of democracy.  The majority may choose to support or oppose anything done by the sovereign in the name of the people by way of exercising the natural rights inherent in the individuals that make up the commonwealth, and if the majority opposes the sovereign then the majority may replace him.  Unfortunately, this interpretation is one of ideals and not one of practicality.  It is entirely possible, through technology and positive law, that a sovereign acquire so much power that a mere majority cannot practically bring enough counter force to bear in order to remove a sovereign.  Reason would seem to imply that a sovereign with such an overabundance of power that could be directed against the people, but does not, would still have the majority of support from the people.  In those cases where the people perceive that a sovereign has abused the use of his acquired power, and it is impractical, or even impossible, due to the power imbalance between the sovereign and the people, for the people to take back their power and give it to a different sovereign, then democracy has failed.
On November 30th, 2011, the United States, through the use of executive/federative powers, exercised its prerogative power by killing, without due process, an American citizen who had chosen, as evidenced by his own actions, to enter into a state of war against America as a whole: Anwar al-Awlaki18.  This action has resulted in an ideological dispute between those who support the actions of the sovereign, who they believe acted for the common good even though it was opposed to standing law requiring the sovereign to refrain from killing one of its own citizens without due process of law, and those who believe the killing was not conducive to the common good because it was in violation of a firm, Constitutional, restriction the people had placed on the sovereign, symbolizing a disrespect for the people who make up the commonwealth and a willingness to violate the agreement for self-serving political gains, or perhaps other reasons unknown to this writer.
On prerogative power:  Prerogative power is nothing more than the power of a sovereign to execute power through an act deemed to be in the best interests of the commonwealth regardless of law19.  This power is designed to eliminate the legislative requirement to foresee every possible eventuality or circumstance, and the best way to deal with those specific circumstances, and enact positive law for the direction of executive power when and if it finds itself in those situations, and because of the understanding that it is impossible to predict all possible future events, the power may be exercised to such a degree that it can violate standing law, as it is argued by some, was the case when the U.S. killed al-Awlaki20.  The same argument might be used if the U.S. were to, in retaliation against Iran, initiate a full scale nuclear strike against the country.  Public perception within a commonwealth is the key to whether or not an executive or federative action is seen as one that promotes the common good or as one that is in opposition to it. 
At this point a question must be asked, based on everything that has come before.  When is the right time for a person or commonwealth to exercise force against the sovereign, to replace him with one more to their liking and who they believe will serve their common interests?  Locke’s response would be that force may only be used against another unlawful and unjust force, and to apply force for any other reason would be unjust and warrant condemnation and retaliation from all within the commonwealth21.  This is not to say that in each instance where the sovereign acts in a manner seen as being unlawfully or unjustly against the preservation of the interests of the commonwealth that the people of the commonwealth will, or should, rise up and replace the sovereign, perhaps through a bloody and long lasting revolution.  Human nature, being what it is, will allow the people to put up with errors and even a few instances of blatant injustice, and will only act with revolutionary force after having been forced over a long period of time to endure suffering and consistent abuses by the sovereign, and after the people have determined there exists the evil intent of the sovereign to actively abuse and make them subject to his arbitrary use of power22.  In short, regarding revolution and civil war, a dispute between the sovereign and a segment of the commonwealth that is of great importance, and where the law is ineffectual, or nonexistent, the only proper judge is the body of the society, and if the sovereign refuses to abide by a judgment against him, he and the commonwealth then enter into a state of war against each other23.
As has been shown, there is a particular circumstance that can cause the failure of democracy as a result of the tensions between the commonwealth and the sovereign.  The circumstance, as has already been stated, is one in which a sizeable majority of force available is controlled and directed by the sovereign against the people, leaving the people practically helpless against the sovereign.  The only way this can be avoided is by the vast majority of the populace having the sovereign under constant and close scrutiny, with remedies under law that allow the people to act quickly and decisively to remove a sovereign seen as unjust, whether in the form of the legislators, the executive, or both.  Also, from the beginning, there must be a system in place, and maintained, that keeps the sovereign from amassing force assets to a degree that the people are at risk of being under the arbitrary rule of a sovereign without having the practical ability to level an equal force in return.  Only then will a sovereign rightly question himself as to whether or not he wishes to enter into a state of war against the people.  The problem is entirely one of “balance of power” between the sovereign and the people.  By dividing the rights, responsibilities and obligations of a selected sovereign; by dividing the legislative powers, the executive powers, the judicial powers, and perhaps other powers amongst various individuals whose primary charge is the self-preservation of the commonwealth, even if action for that end is opposed to their own self-preservation, a commonwealth has a system in place well suited for its purpose.  Unfortunately, the system described is not enough by itself.  Unless the people are also vigilant and aware of the acts of the sovereign, and it is possible that this may not happen as a result of apathy or ignorance, the sovereign may be able to acquire enough tools of force that by the time the people realize they are powerless to stop an unjust sovereign, it will be too late.

Endnotes-Citations
1.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 4. P. 3.
2.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 6. P. 4.
3.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 6. P. 4-5.
4.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 7. P. 5.
5.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 8. P. 5.
6.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 13. P. 8.
7.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 13. P. 9.
8.      Second Treatise. Chapter 2. Section 15. P. 9-10.
9.      Second Treatise. Chapter 4. Section 22. P. 15.
10.    Second Treatise. Chapter 11. Section 135. P. 82-83.
11.    Second Treatise. Chapter 13. Section 149. P. 92.
12.    Second Treatise. Chapter 12. Section 144. P. 89.
13.    Second Treatise. Chapter 12. Section 143. P. 89.
14.    Second Treatise. Chapter 12. Section 145. P. 90.
15.    Second Treatise. Chapter 12. Section 146. P. 90.
16.   Wall Street Journal. Wednesday, October 12, 2011. P. 1. Print.
17.    Oxford English Dictionary.  Oxford University Press.  Second edition.  1989.  Online version September 2011.  Web.  10 Oct 2011.
18.   Wall Street Journal. Saturday/Sunday, October 1-2, 2011. P. 1. Print.
19.   Second Treatise. Chapter 13. Section 158. P. 98.
20.   Second Treatise. Chapter 14. Section 159. P. 99.
21.   Second Treatise. Chapter 23. Section 201. P. 126.
22.   Second Treatise. Chapter 29. Section 225. P. 138.
23.   Second Treatise. Chapter 29. Section 242. P.148.